QUESTION
English course VERSION 2
1
PHIL/LING/COMS 2504-A: Language and Communication
Paper information and topics sheet, Summer 2020
OVERVIEW AND GENERAL INSTRUCTIONS
Please read and follow these instructions carefully.
Your paper should be approximately 1500 words long. You won’t be penalized for being slightly (~100 words) under or over the word count but please do not substantially surpass this word limit. The paper is worth 30% of your final course grade. The paper workshop assignment contributes an additional 5% to your final course grade.
Your work will be graded on both style and content (see grading rubric for clarification). Your papers should demonstrate a strong grasp of the directly relevant material as well as some background concepts and debates, and you are expected to state and defend a clear thesis.
Keep in mind that successfully defending a position requires giving strong reasons for holding that position, as well as considering and responding to at least one objection. While it is most important for you to write clearly, accurately, and rigorously on the relevant material, you are also encouraged to demonstrate some original thought and, where possible, to use your own examples to help support your analysis and argument.
TEXT USE AND CITATION
It is extremely important that you cite all your sources. I’m not picky about citation style; just make sure that your citations are clear, specific, and reasonably consistent. Keep in mind that you must cite page numbers when quoting or directly paraphrasing the material.
You are not expected to use external sources but are free to do so. In any case, you should be mainly drawing on the course material. If your sources are all from the course and have the same pagination as the course texts, you do not need to include a separate references page. If you do use any outside or different sources, you must include a references list with full bibliographic information for each source.
The topic list covers material up to and including Tuesday July 28th (paper deadline). Whichever topic you choose, you are expected to apply course concepts and to draw directly and substantially at least two course readings (assigned up to and including July 28th). *NOTE: since some topics require familiarity with readings we have not yet covered in class as of July 21st (workshop class), I encourage you to read ahead if needed; I will post the relevant slides before the workshop*
FORMAT AND SUBMISSION REQUIREMENTS
Please submit the paper as a Word document, as this facilitates providing comments via tracked changes. Your papers should be written in 12-point font and double-spaced. You do not need a title page. At the top of your first page, indicate your full name and/or student number, the topic number, the date, and your word count.
You will be submitting your papers via cuLearn by Thursday July 28th 11:59pm. Without an extension, papers received after this date will be deducted by 3% per day for a maximum of five days, after which they will receive a zero. Extensions must be requested before the deadline has passed. 2
ASSISTANCE WITH THE PAPER
Please consult cuLearn for the instructor’s and TA’s office hours. I encourage you to take advantage of our availability wherever possible. I also recommend that you consult the philosophy paper grading rubric and this resource on philosophical writing, both of which are available on cuLearn: http://www.jimpryor.net/teaching/guidelines/writing.html
PAPER WORKSHOP
As indicated on the syllabus, half of our class on Tuesday July 21st will be devoted to a workshop that is designed to support your paper writing process. I will expect you to have chosen a topic and put some ideas down in writing; your rough work can be just a brainstorm or very sketchy outline–as long as you’ve thought about it and have some notes.
You will draw on your rough work for both the workshop exercises, which include independent and peer-supported activities, as well as the workshop assignment, which is completed as a group and submitted (one copy per group) at the end of class. Your workshop assignment will be graded on its clarity and detail as well as its demonstration of critical thinking, reflection, and collaboration.
TOPICS
Following the guidelines indicated above and in the writing resources posted to cuLearn as well as the paper workshop, respond to one of the following four prompts in an argumentative paper:
- Outline and defend one of the theories of linguistic meaning that we have examined in the course. This will include assessing at least one criticism of the theory we examined in the course and providing a response to that criticism.
- Drawing on relevant philosophers and using your own example(s), explain the distinction between attributive and referential uses of definite descriptions, as well as the broader debate from which this distinction emerged. Outline and support a position in this debate.
- Drawing on an original example or set of examples and the views of 2-3 philosophers we have examined in class (e.g., Davidson and Grice), outline and defend an account of how communication is cooperative.
- Using your own example(s) of malapropisms in action and drawing on his notions of prior and passing theory, explain how and why Davidson concludes that there is no such thing as a language (as we tend to know it). Outline and defend your position on his view.
Subject | Language Acquisition | Pages | 8 | Style | APA |
---|
Answer
Communication is Cooperative
Drawing on an original example or set of examples and the views of 2-3 philosophers we have examined in class (e.g., Davidson and Grice), outline and defend an account of how communication is cooperative.
In the field of linguistics, the cooperative principle provides a description of how people achieve an effective conversational communication when faced by common social circumstances. This can include how the speakers and the listeners cooperate and mutually accept each other to be understood in a specific manner. Taking into consideration the sentiments of Paul Grice, the linguist who introduced the pragmatic theory, it is evident that one should make a contribution when needed at the phase where it takes place, and by the accepted aim of direction of the communication exchange in which an individual is engaged (Grice, 1975). According to Nordquist (2019), within a conversation process, the cooperative principle refers to the assumption that the conversation participants normally strive to be truthful, informative, clear and relevant. Davidson’s philosophy of language is founded on conceptual connections as the linguist draws between the traditional questions on issues and language originating from other philosophical perspectives. For instance, Davidson draws connection from action theory, philosophy of the mind, metaphysics and epistemology (Davidson, 1986). This essay explores the views of Davidson and Grice and identifies a set of examples from the work of the philosophers to defend a stand of the cooperative communication principle.
Grice’s Stand on Cooperative Communication
Communication is cooperative because all the conversation participants can establish that a maxim has been broken by the communicator or the writer on purpose to establish new meaning which can be derived through inference (Grice, 1975). According to Grice (1975), people will always engage in assumptions whenever they communicate. However, it is a fact that they engage in the assumptions without their knowledge that the persons that they are conversing with are conversationally cooperative. This factor suggests that the people will cooperate with an aim of attaining a mutual conversational end. The conversation cooperation is also effective in the events when people are not socially cooperative (Grice, 1975). For instance, people can engage in an argument and still cooperate conversationally to achieve the argument.
The conversational cooperation, as outlined by Grice, is manifested under several conversational maxims which people should take into consideration. The maxis consider the first sight as rules. However, they later seem to be broken more often in comparison to the phonological or grammatical rules. This provides an explanation why Grice utilizes the word “maxim” rather than “rule.” According to Grice (1975), when engaging in a conversation, people adhere to the following maxims. The first one includes the quantity maxim. In this case, people remain cooperative when most of the information they provide is considered as helpful. To illustrate this, Grice (1975) implies that this maxim is similar to a baby bear porridge temperature which is just the right amount. For instance, one may feel like a magazine site offers too much information. However, the company is remaining cooperative by trying to be honest and helpful.
Grice (1975) also suggests that the conversational cooperation can also be achieved by being honest and helpful. The major focus of this maxim is to communicate a truthful message to maintain the cooperation principle. Despite the fact that the quality maxim seems complicated, it is considered simple to follow. Notably, this maxim is founded on an advantage that people will find it difficult to lie in the events when they are directly questioned. Arguably, this is founded on a belief that in most cases, people will communicate without thinking, especially when communicating a written message. This is founded on the fact that writers normally have more time to think about the information they are relaying in comparison to the speakers (Grice, 1975).
The relation maxim provides a depiction that people will cooperate when engaging in a conversation by remaining relevant. Evidently, when a person joins a conversation, they simply cannot start talking without having an idea of the message they are communicating. It is mandatory that one should take time to connect to the conversation to ensure that the message being relayed is relevant to the topic under discussion. For example, when people are talking about taking a vacation and a person want to talk about Mexico, the two topics should connect. For instance, one can make a statement such as “the last time I took a leave from work; I went to Mexico for a vacation.”
Grice (1975) presents the maxim of manner to support the conversational principle argument by depicting that people should always communicate their message in the clearest, briefest and the most orderly way to achieve the requirement of cooperation. One of the best illustrations for this maxim includes the fact that a person can get penalized for writing an essay in vague manner which results to the loss of marks. Evidently, when one writes an overly wordy essay, chances are higher that the writer will lose marks because the reader will get bored of going through the essay to understand the message being relayed. Despite the fact that one does not lose marks when engaging in a conversation, it is highly likely that one will lose friends when he/she fails to follow the presented maxims.
Davidson’s Stand on Cooperative Communication
Davidson maintains a view that what contributes to the aesthetic nature of the conversation is what has to do with the nature of the interaction which takes place between the people who engage in a conversation (Carroll, 1992). An effective orientation stemming from the conversationalists can be effective in establishing an effective communication. However, this will not provide a guarantee that the level of interaction between conventionalists will provide a desirable aesthetic experience.
Evident, an aesthetic form of conversation should maintain a specific form of structure. Notably, Davidson’s work in relation to the communication complexities builds on Dewey’s arguments related to aesthetic communication (Bresnahan, 2014). Notably, Davidson has taken a more fundamental look at how people engaging in conversation interact to achieve the aesthetic communication requirement. According to Davidson (1986), the views provides an emphasis on the indispensable role attached to the conventions and the rule governing practices associated with linguist that meaning cannot offer a complete picture regarding how one can successfully communicate. Davidson indicates that the views fail to consider the linguistic phenomenon such as novel sayings and malapropisms which are experienced in the events when the conventions are broken unintentionally or deliberately (Davidson, 2005). Besides drawing his arguments from Dewey’s work, Davidson also draws connection from action theory, philosophy of the mind, metaphysics and epistemology
Following Grice’s provisions, Davidson establishes a view which further connects the meaning of what a speaker says with his/her intentions. The speaker is required to consider the readiness of the interlocutor with an aim of ensuring an effective form of interpretation. According to Davidson (1986), this is referred to as the interpretability requirement. Arguably, this involves offering sufficient clues or taking actions which directs the conversation to a direction that one requires the listeners to grasp the meaning being communicated. To cooperate, it is evident that the linguistic conventions do not impose a limit which can be easily determined depending on the ways in which the speaker makes himself interpretable. To illustrate this factor, Davidson relied on the linguistic experiments completed by Joyce on Finnegan Wake and Ulysses. In this case, Davidson observes that even with enough creativity, it is difficult to establish how much the use of language can maintain its meaning even by deviating from the standard.
Furthermore, by drawing a distinction between the passing and the prior theory in linguistic, Davidson maintains that the theoretical frameworks have varied roles to play depending on the perspective being explored. This can be the speaker’s perspective, listener or the conversation itself. Notably, the passing theory is considered as the true finding point of the communication process since it determines how the communicator will express the message being communicated to attain the required meaning based on the speakers’ words.
References
Bresnahan, A. (2014). Toward A Deweyan Theory of Ethical and Aesthetic Performing Arts Practice, Journal of Aesthetics and Phenomenology 1, 2, 133-148.
Carroll, N. (1992). “Art, Intention, and Conversation,” in Intention and Interpretation, ed. Gary Iseminger. Philadelphia: Temple University Press
Davidson, D. (1986). “A nice derangement of epitaphs,” reprinted in the essential Davidson. Oxford University Press.
Davidson, D. (2005). “A Nice Derangement of Epitaphs,” in his Truth, Language, and History. Oxford: Clarendon Press
Grice, P. (1975). “Logic and conversation”. In Cole, P.; Morgan, J. (eds.). Syntax and semantics. 3: Speech acts. New York: Academic Press. pp. 41–58
Nordquist, R. (2019). The Cooperative Principle in Conversation. Thoughtco. Retrieved from https://www.thoughtco.com/cooperative-principle-conversation-1689928
Related Samples
The Role of Essay Writing Services in Online Education: A Comprehensive Analysis
Introduction The...
Write Like a Pro: Effective Strategies for Top-Notch Explication Essays
Introduction "A poem...
How to Conquer Your Exams: Effective Study Strategies for All Learners
Introduction Imagine...
Overcoming Writer’s Block: Strategies to Get Your Essays Flowing
Introduction The...
Optimizing Your Online Learning Experience: Tips and Tricks for Success
The world of education...